INDEX.

Abstraction

not source of ideas of primary qualities, 122.

Academic

philosophy, 34.

Action

and philosophy, 1, 4, 34, 128;

Addition

4.

Analogy

a species of, the foundation of all reasoning about matter of fact, 82;

Animals

the reason of, 83-85;

learn from experience and draw inferences, 83;

which can only be founded on custom, 84;

cause of difference between men and animals, 84 n.

Antiquity

62.

Appearances

to senses must be corrected by reason, 117.

A priori

25, 36 n, 89 n, 132, 132 n.

Aristotle

4.

Association

of ideas, three principles of, 18-19, 41-44 (v. Cause C).

Atheism

116.

Bacon

99.

Belief

(v. Cause C, 39-45);

and chance, 46.

Berkeley

really a sceptic, 122 n.

Bigotry

102.

Body

and soul, mystery of union of, 52;

volition and movements of, 52.

Real existence of (v. Scepticism, B, 118-123).

Cause

first (v. God, Necessity, 78-81; Providence, 102-115, 132 n).

a principle of association of ideas, 19, 43;

sole foundation of reasonings about matter of fact or real existence, 22.

A. Knowledge of Causes arises from experience not from Reason, 23-33.

Reasonings a priori give no knowledge of cause and effect, 23 f.;

impossible to see the effect in the cause since they are totally different, 25;

natural philosophy never pretends to assign ultimate causes, but only to reduce causes to a few general causes, e.g. gravity, 26;

geometry applies laws obtained by experience, 27.

Conclusions from experience not based on any process of the understanding, 28;

yet we infer in the future a similar connexion between known qualities of things and their secret powers, to that which we assumed in the past. On what is this inference based? 29;

demonstrative reasoning has no place here, and all experimental reasoning assumes the resemblance of the future to the past, and so cannot prove it without being circular, 30, 32;

if reasoning were the basis of this belief, there would be no need for the multiplication of instances or of long experience, 31;

yet conclusions about matter of fact are affected by experience even in beasts and children, so that they cannot be founded on abstruse reasoning, 33;

to explain our inferences from experience a principle is required of equal weight and authority with reason, 34.

B. Custom enables us to infer existence of one object from the appearance of another, 35-38.

Experience enables us to ascribe a more than arbitrary connexion to objects, 35;

we are determined to this by custom or habit which is the great guide of human life, 36;

but our inference must be based on some fact present to the senses or memory, 37;

the customary conjunction between such an object and some other object produces an operation of the soul which is as unavoidable as love, 38;

animals also infer one event from another by custom, 82-84;

and in man as in animals experimental reasoning depends on a species of instinct or mechanical power that acts in us unknown to ourselves, 85.

C. Belief, 39-45.

Belief differs from fiction or the loose reveries of the fancy by some feeling annexed to it, 39;

belief cannot be defined, but may be described as a more lively, forcible, firm, steady conception of an object than can be attained by the imagination alone, 40;

it is produced by the principles of association, viz. resemblance, 41;

contiguity, 42;

causation, 43;

by a kind of pre-established harmony between the course of nature and our ideas, 44;

this operation of our minds necessary to our subsistence and so entrusted by nature to instinct rather than to reasoning, 45.

Probability, 46-7.

Belief produced by a majority of chances by an inexplicable contrivance of Nature, 46 (cf. 87-8);

probability of causes: the failure of a cause ascribed to a secret counteracting cause, 47 (cf. 67);

it is universally allowed that chance when strictly examined is a mere negative word, 74.

D. Power, 49-57.

Power, force, energy, necessary connexion must either be defined by analysis or explained by production of the impression from which they are copied, 49;

from the first appearance of an object we cannot foretell its effect: we cannot see the power of a single body: we only see sequence, 50.

Is the idea of power derived from an internal impression and is it an idea of reflection? 51;

it is not derived, as Locke said, from reasoning about power of production in nature, 50 n;

nor from consciousness of influence of will over bodily organs, 52;

nor from effort to overcome resistance, 52 n (cf. 60 n);

nor from influence of will over mind, 53;

many philosophers appeal to an invisible intelligent principle, to a volition of the supreme being, and regard causes as only occasions and our mental conceptions as revelations, 54-5;

thus diminishing the grandeur of God, 56;

this theory too bold and beyond verification by our faculties, and is no explanation, 57;

vis inertiae, 57 n.

In single instances we only see sequence of loose events which are conjoined and never connected, 58;

the idea of necessary connexion only arises from a number of similar instances, and the only difference between such a number and a single instance is that the former produces a habit of expecting the usual attendant, 59, 61.

This customary transition is the impression from which we form the idea of necessary connexion.

E. Reasoning from effect to cause and conversely, 105-115 (v. Providence).

In arguing from effect to cause we must not infer more qualities in the cause than are required to produce the effect, nor reason backwards from an inferred cause to new effects, 105-8;

we can reason back from cause to new effects in the case of human acts by analogy which rests on previous knowledge, 111-2;

when the effect is entirely singular and does not belong to any species we cannot infer its cause at all, 115.

F. Definitions of Cause, 60 (cf. 74 n).

Ceremonies

41.

Chance

ignorance of causes, 46;

has no existence, 74 (v. Cause B).

Cicero

4.

Circle

in reasoning, 30.

Clarke

37 n.

Colour

peculiarity of ideas of, 16.

Contiguity

19, 42.

Contradiction

the test of demonstration, 132.

Contrariety

19 n.

Contrary

of matter of fact always possible, 21, 132.

Creation

132 n.

Criticism

132.

Cudworth

57 n, 158 n.

Custom

when strongest conceals itself, 24;

an ultimate principle of all conclusions from experience, 36, 127;

and belief, 39-45;

gives rise to inferences of animals, 84.

Definition

only applicable to complex ideas, 49;

need of, 131;

of cause, 60.

Demonstrative

opp. intuitive, 20;

reasoning, 30;

confined to quantity and number, 131;

impossible to demonstrate a fact since no negation of a fact can involve a contradiction, 132.

Descartes

57 n.;

his universal doubt antecedent to study if strictly taken is incurable, since even from an indubitable first principle no advance can be made except by the faculties which we doubt, 116;

his appeal to the veracity of God is useless, 120 (v. Scepticism, 116-132).

Design

argument from, 105 f. (v. Providence).

Divisibility

of mathematical and physical points, 124.

Doubt

Cartesian, 116, 120 (v. Scepticism A).

Epictetus

34.

Epicurean

philosophy, defence of, 102-15;

denial of providence and future state is harmless, 104 (v. Providence).

Euclid

truths in, do not depend on existence of circles or triangles, 20.

Evidence

moral and natural, 70;

value of human, 82-9 (v. Miracles).

Evil

doctrine of necessity either makes God the cause of evil or denies existence of evil as regards the whole, 78-81.

Existence

external and perception, 118-9 (v. Scepticism, B, 116-32).

Ex nihilo nihil

132 n.

Experience

(v. Cause A, 23-33);

opposition of reason and experience usual, but really erroneous and superficial, 36 n.

Infallible, may be regarded as proof, 87 (v. Miracles);

all the philosophy and religion in the world cannot carry us beyond the usual course of experience, 113.

Extension

50;

a supposed primary quality, 122.

Faith

101, 132.

Fiction

and fact (v. Cause C), 39 f.

Future

inference to, from past, 29 (v. Cause A).

General

ideas, do not really exist, but only particular ideas attached to a general term, 125 n.

Geography

mental, 8.

Geometry

propositions of certain, as depending only on relations of ideas not on existence of objects, 20;

gives no knowledge of ultimate causes: only applies laws discovered by experience, 27.

God

idea of, 14;

no idea of except what we learn from reflection on our own faculties, 57;

theory that God is cause of all motion and thought, causes being only occasions of his volition, 54-57;

by doctrine of necessity either there are no bad actions or God is the cause of evil, 78-81.

Veracity of, appealed to, 120.

And creation of matter, 132 n.

v. Providence, 102-115; Scepticism, 116-132.

Golden

age, 107.

Gravity

26.

Habit

(v. Custom, Cause B).

History

use of, 65.

Human

nature, inconstancy a constant character of, 68.

Ideas

A. Origin of, 11-17.

Perceptions divided into impressions and ideas, 11-12;

the mind can only compound the materials derived from outward or inward sentiment, 13 (cf. 53);

all ideas resolvable into simple ideas copied from precedent feelings, 14;

deficiency in an organ of sensation produces deficiency in corresponding idea, 15-16;

suspected ideas to be tested by asking for the impression from which it is derived, 17 (cf. 49);

idea of reflection, 51;

general ideas, 135 n;

innate ideas, 19 n;

power of will over ideas, 53.

B. Association of, 18-19.

Ideas introduce each other with a certain degree of method and regularity, 18;

only three principles of association, viz. Resemblance, Contiguity, and Cause or Effect, 19;

contrariety, 19 n;

production of belief by these principles, 41-43.

C. Correspondence of ideas and course of nature, 44;

relations of ideas one of two possible objects of enquiry, 20;

such relations discoverable by the mere operation of thought, 20, 131;

no demonstration possible except in case of ideas of quantity or number, 131.

Imagination

11, 39;

and belief, 40.

Impressions

all our more lively perceptions, 12;

the test of ideas, 17, 49.

Incest

peculiar turpitude of explained, 12.

Inconceivability

of the negative, 132 (cf. 20).

Inertia

57 n.

Inference

and similarity, 30, 115 (v. Cause).

Infinite

divisibility, 124 f.

Instances

multiplication of not required by reason, 31.

Instinct

more trustworthy than reasoning, 45;

the basis of all experimental reasoning, 85;

the basis of realism, 118, 121.

Intuitive

opp. mediate reasoning, 2.

La Bruyere

4.

Liberty

(v. Necessity, 62-97).

Definition of hypothetical liberty, 73.

Necessary to morality, 77.

Locke

4, 40 n, 50 n, 57 n.

His loose use of 'ideas,' 19 n;

betrayed into frivolous disputes about innate ideas by the School-men, 19 n;

distinction of primary and secondary qualities, 122.

Malebranche

4, 57 n..

Man

a reasonable and active being, 4.

Marriage

rules of, based on and vary with utility, 118.

Mathematics

ideas of, clear and determinate, hence their superiority to moral and metaphysical sciences, 48;

their difficulty, 48.

Mathematical and physical points, 124 n.

Matter

necessity of, 64;

creation of, 132 n (v. Scepticism A).

Matter-of-fact

contrary of, always possible, 21;

arguments to new, based only on cause and effect, 22.

Metaphysics

not a science, 5-6;

how inferior and superior to mathematics, 48.

Mind

mental geography, 8;

secret springs and principles of, 9;

can only mix and compound materials given by inward and outward sentiment, 13;

power of will over, 53.

Miracles.

86-101.

Belief in human evidence diminishes according as the event witnessed is unusual or extraordinary, 89;

difference between extraordinary and miraculous, 89 n;

if the evidence for a miracle amounted to proof we should have one proof opposed by another proof, for the proof against a miracle is as complete as possible;

an event is not miraculous unless there is a uniform experience, that is a proof, against it, 90;

definition of miracle, 90 n;

hence no testimony is sufficient to establish a miracle unless its falsehood would be more miraculous than the event it establishes, 91;

as a fact the evidence for a miracle has never amounted to proof, 92;

the passion for the wonderful in human nature, 93;

prevalence of miracles in savage and early periods and their diminution with civilization, 94;

the evidence for miracles in matters of religion opposed by the almost infinite number of witnesses for rival religions, 95;

value of human testimony diminished by temptation to pose as a prophet or apostle, 97;

no testimony for a miracle has ever amounted to a probability, much less to a proof, and if it did amount to a proof it would be opposed by another perfect proof, 98;

so a miracle can never be proved so as to be the foundation of a system of religion, 99;

a conclusion which confounds those who base the Christian religion on reason, not on faith, 100;

the Christian religion cannot be believed without a miracle which will subvert the principle of a man's understanding and give him a determination to believe what is most contrary to custom and experience, 101.

Moral

evil (q.v.) 80.

Moral science

30;

inferior to mathematics, 48;

sceptical objections to, 126-7.

Moral evidence easily combined with natural, 70.

Motion

50.

Nature

design in, 105 f. (v. Providence),

and the course of our ideas, 44.

State of, a philosophical fiction, 151, 151 n.

Necessary

connexion (v. Cause).

Necessity

two definitions of, 75.

A. and Liberty, 62-81;

the controversy is based on ambiguity, and all mankind have always been of the same opinion on this subject, 63;

our idea of the necessity of matter arises solely from observed uniformity and consequent inference, circumstances which are allowed by all men to exist in respect of human action, 64;

history and knowledge of human nature assume such uniformity, 65,

which does not exclude variety due to education and progress, 66;

irregular actions to be explained by secret operation of contrary causes, 67;

the inconstancy of human action, its constant character, as of winds and weather, 68;

we all acknowledge and draw inferences from the regular conjunction of motives and actions, 69;

history, politics, and morals show this, and the possibility of combining moral and natural evidence shows that they have a common origin, 70;

the reluctance to acknowledge the necessity of actions due to a lingering belief that we can see real connexion behind mere conjunction, 71;

we should begin with the examination not of the soul and will but of brute matter, 72;

the prevalence of the liberty doctrine due to a false sensation of liberty and a false experiment, 72 n;

though this question is the most contentious of all, mankind has always agreed in the doctrine of liberty, if we mean by it that hypothetical liberty which consists in a power of acting or not acting according to the determinations of our will, and which can be ascribed to every one who is not a prisoner, 73;

liberty when opposed to necessity, and not merely to constraint, is the same as chance, 74.

B. Both necessity and liberty are necessary to morality, this doctrine of necessity only alters our view of matter and so is at least innocent, 75;

rewards and punishments imply the uniform influence of motives, and connexion of character and action: if necessity be denied, a man may commit any crime and be no worse for it, 76;

liberty also essential to morality, 77.

Objection that doctrine of necessity and of a regular chain of causes either makes God the cause of evil, or abolishes evil in actions, 78;

Stoic answer, that the whole system is good, is specious but ineffectual in practice, 79;

no speculative argument can counteract the impulse of our natural sentiments to blame certain actions, 80;

how God can be the cause of all actions without being the author of moral evil is a mystery with which philosophy cannot deal, 81.

Negative

inconceivability of, 132.

Newton

57 n.

Nisus

52 n, 60 n.

Number

the object of demonstration, 131.

Occasional causes

theory of, 55.

Parallelism

between thought and course of nature, 44-5.

Perception

and external objects, 119 f. (v. Scepticism, Impression, Idea).

Philosophy

moral, two branches of, abstruse and practical, 1-5;

gratifies innocent curiosity, 6;

metaphysics tries to deal with matters inaccessible to human understanding, 6.

True, must lay down limits of understanding, 7 (cf. 113);

a large part of, consists in mental geography, 8;

may hope to resolve principles of mind into still more general principles, 9.

Natural, only staves off our ignorance a little longer, as moral or metaphysical philosophy serves only to discover larger portions of it, 26;

academical, or sceptical, flatters no bias or passion except love of truth, and so has few partisans, 34;

though it destroy speculation, cannot destroy action, for nature steps in and asserts her rights, 34;

moral, inferior to mathematics in clearness of ideas, superior in shortness of arguments, 48.

Controversies in, due to ambiguity of terms, 62.

Disputes in, not be settled by appeal to dangerous consequences of a doctrine, 75.

Speculative, entirely indifferent to the peace of society and security of government, 104 (cf. 114).

All the philosophy in the world, and all the religion in the world, which is nothing but a species of philosophy, can never carry us beyond the usual course of experience, 113.

Happiness of, to have originated in an age and country of freedom and toleration, 102.

Points

physical, indivisible, 124 n.

Power

50 f, 60 n. (v. Cause D).

Probability

46 f. (v. Cause, B).

Probable

arguments, 38, 46 n.

Production

50 n.

Promises

not the foundation of justice, 257.

Proof

46 n, 86-101 (v. Miracles, Demonstrative).

Providence

102-115 (v. God).

The sole argument for a divine existence is from the marks of design in nature; must not infer greater power in the cause than is necessary to produce the observed effects, nor argue from such an inferred cause to any new effects which have not been observed, 105;

so must not infer in God more power, wisdom, and benevolence than appears in nature, 106;

so it is unnecessary to try and save the honour of the Gods by assuming the intractability of matter or the observance of general laws, 107;

to argue from effects to unknown causes, and then from these causes to unknown effects, is a gross sophism, 108.

From imperfect exercise of justice in this world we cannot infer its perfect exercise in a future world, 109;

we must regulate our conduct solely by the experienced train of events, 110;

in case of human works of art we can infer the perfect from the imperfect, but that is because we know man by experience and also know other instances of his art, 111-112;

but in the case of God we only know him by his productions, and do not know any class of beings to which he belongs, 113;

and the universe, his production, is entirely singular and does not belong to a known species of things, 115.

Punishment

requires doctrines of necessity and liberty, 76 (v. Necessity).

Pyrrhonism

126.

Qualities

primary and secondary, 122.

Quantity

and number, the only objects of demonstration, the parts of them being entirely similar, 131.

Real

presence, 86.

Reality

and thought, 44.

Realism

of the vulgar, 118.

Reason

(a) opp. intuition, 29;

opp. experience, 28, 36 n.

(b) Corrects sympathy and senses, 117.

No match for nature, 34.

Fallacious, compared with instinct, 45.

Of men and animals, 84 n.

(c) attempts to destroy, by reasoning, 124;

objections to abstract reasoning, 124 f. (v. Scepticism).

(d) Reasoning.

Two kinds of, demonstrative and moral, 30, 46 n, 132;

moral, divided into general and particular, 132;

produces demonstrations, proofs, and probabilities, 46 n.

Probable (v. Cause, 28-32).

Relations

of ideas, discoverable by the mere operation of thought, independently of the existence of any object, 20.

Religion

a kind of philosophy, 113 (v. Miracles, Providence).

Resemblance

19, 41 (v. Similarity).

Resistance

and idea of power, 53 n.

Scepticism

A. antecedent to study and philosophy, such as Descartes' universal doubt of our faculties, would be incurable: in a more moderate sense it is useful, 116 (cf. 129-30);

extravagant attempts of, to destroy reason by reasoning, 124.

No such absurd creature as a man who has no opinion about anything at all, 116;

admits of no answer and produces no conviction, 122 n. (cf. 34, 126, 128).

B. As to the Senses, 117-123.

The ordinary criticisms of our senses only show that they have to be corrected by Reason, 117;

more profound arguments show that the vulgar belief in external objects is baseless, and that the objects we see are nothing but perceptions which are fleeting copies of other existences, 118;

even this philosophy is hard to justify; it appeals neither to natural instinct, nor to experience, for experience tells nothing of objects which perceptions resemble, 119;

the appeal to the veracity of God is useless, 120;

and scepticism is here triumphant, 121.

The distinction between primary and secondary qualities is useless, for the supposed primary qualities are only perceptions, 122;

and Berkeley's theory that ideas of primary qualities are obtained by abstraction is impossible, 122, 122 n;

if matter is deprived of both primary and secondary qualities there is nothing left except a mere something which is not worth arguing about, 123.

C. As to Reason, 124-130.

Attempt to destroy Reason by reasoning extravagant, 124;

objection to abstract reasoning because it asserts infinite divisibility of extension which is shocking to common sense, 124,

and infinite divisibility of time, 125;

yet the ideas attacked are so clear and distinct that scepticism becomes sceptical about itself, 125.

Popular objections to moral reasoning about matter of fact, based on weakness of understanding, variation of judgement, and disagreement among men, confuted by action, 126;

philosophical objections, that we only experience conjunction and that inference is based on custom, 127;

excessive scepticism refuted by its uselessness and put to flight by the most trivial event in life, 128.

Mitigated scepticism or academical philosophy useful as a corrective and as producing caution and modesty, 129;

and as limiting understanding to proper objects, 130;

all reasoning which is not either abstract, about quantity and number, or experimental, about matters of fact, is sophistry and illusion, 132.

D, In Religion (v. Miracles, Providence).

Sciences

132 (v. Reason, (d); Scepticism, C).

Secret

powers, 39;

counteracting causes, 47, 67.

Senses

outward and inward sensation supplies all the materials of thinking--must be corrected by reason, 117.

Scepticism concerning, 117 (v. Scepticism, B).

Similarity

basis of all arguments from experience, 31 (cf. 115).

Solidity

50;

a supposed primary quality, 122.

Soul

and body, 52.

Space

and time, 124 f.

Species

an effect which belongs to no species does not admit of inference to its cause, 115 (cf. 113).

Stoics

34, 79.

Superstition

6 (v. Providence).

Theology

science of, 132 (v. God, Providence).

Tillotson

argument against real presence, 86.

Time

and space, 124 f.

Truth

8, 17 (v. Scepticism).

Understanding

limits of human, 7;

operations of, to be classified, 8;

opp. experience, 28;

weakness of, 126 (v. Reason, Scepticism).

Voluntariness

as ground of distinction between virtues and talents, 130.

Whole

theory that everything is good as regards 'the whole,' 79 80.

Will

compounds materials given by senses, 13;

influence of over organs of body can never give us the idea of power; for we are not conscious of any power in our will, only of sequence of motions on will, 52;

so with power of will over our minds in raising up new ideas, 53.

Of God, cannot be used to explain motion, 57.

Freedom of (v. Necessity).

*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK AN ENQUIRY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE

Share on Twitter Share on Facebook